Austin’s Speech Act Theory and the Speech Situation Sample

Table of Content

THalf a century ago. John Austin gave a series of talks. the William James Lectures at Harvard. which were published posthumously as a book entitled How to Make Thingss with Words. Austin presented a new image of analyzing significance ; significance is described in a relation among lingual conventions correlated with words/sentences. the state of affairs where the talker really says something to the listener. and associated purposes of the talker. The thought that intending exists among these dealingss is depicted successfully by the construct of Acts of the Apostless: in expressing a sentence. that is. in utilizing lingual conventions. the talker with an associated purpose performs a lingual act to the listener. Austin’s analysis of significance is alone in the sense that significance is non explained through some signifiers of decrease.

In reductive theories of significance. complexnesss of intending expressed by a sentence are reduced by a individual standard to something else. and this is claimed to be the procedure of explicating the significance of the sentence. We can happen this reductive «explanation» of intending typically in Russell: utilizing a logical/mathematical theoretical account. Russell reduces the significance of a sentence to a fact to which the sentence corresponds. The strictest reductionists are logical rationalists. Harmonizing to Warnock ( 1969 ) . by «verification principles» logical rationalists reduced complexnesss of sentence significance to something «verifiable» . and condemned an unobjective sentence as. purely talking. bunk. Tarski besides took a reductive attack and defined the significance of a sentence in footings of a province of personal businesss to which the sentence corresponds. Modern truth-conditional semioticians adopt the Russellian thought of explicating

This essay could be plagiarized. Get your custom essay
“Dirty Pretty Things” Acts of Desperation: The State of Being Desperate
128 writers

ready to help you now

Get original paper

Without paying upfront

Testi the significance of a sentence and the Russellian/Tarskian thought of correlating a sentence. as its significance. with a fact or province of personal businesss. Dowty. Wall. and Peters ( 1985 ) say. to explicate the significance of a sentence is «to stipulate its truth conditions. i. e. . to give necessary and sufficient conditions for the truth of that sentence» . Austin. on the other manus. tried to depict «the entire address act in the entire address situation» and warned against oversimplifying complexnesss of significance. in peculiar. by cut downing intending to descriptive significance:

It has come to be seen that many specially confusing words embedded in seemingly descriptive statements do non function to bespeak some specially uneven extra characteristic in the world reported. but to bespeak ( non to describe ) the fortunes in which the statement is made or reserves to which it is capable or the manner in which it is to be taken and the similar. To overlook these possibilities in the manner one time common is called the «descriptive» false belief.

Through a description of the success/failure of the address act purported. which is explained as a violation/observation of the felicitousness conditions. Austin formulated a method to depict a sentence in footings of the address state of affairs where it is uttered: by agencies of associated lingual conventions. the talker. with an associated purpose. really performs an act to the listener. which induces a certain response from the listener.

As we will develop subsequently. Austin’s thought can be interpreted in the undermentioned manner: by expressing a performative sentence. the talker indicates a certain address state of affairs where ( I ) a certain convention exists. as shown by the felicitousness status ( A. 1 ) . ( II ) there are certain individuals and fortunes. as shown by the felicitousness status ( A. 2 ) . ( III ) the talker performs the act in a certain manner. as shown by the felicitousness status ( B. 1 ).

work. the success of the purported address act is explained as an designation of the present address state of affairs with the address state of affairs indicated by the performative sentence. The failure of the purported address act is. on the other manus. explained as a spread between the present address state of affairs and the address state of affairs indicated. We will lucubrate on this later.

Austin so delineates the construct of performativity. He shows that performativity does non conflict with statements as the initial differentiation between performatives and constatives suggests. In its drawn-out sense. performativity is interpreted as a quintessential characteristic of communicating which is expressed with legion verbs. So even expressing a sentence of «I province …» can be infelicitous in six different ways in the same mode as expressing a sentence with a performative verb. For illustration. we can conceive of a linguistic communication whose vocabulary lacks a verb with a sense of «to state» in English. although it has verbs with a sense of «to make a sound» . «to utter» . or «to say» .

The talker of the linguistic communication can non execute the same act that the English talker would execute in expressing the sentence «I province …» . hence go againsting the felicitousness status ( A. 1 ) . although it is rather likely that she can execute similar Acts of the Apostless or accomplish similar effects by expressing the sentence with alternate verbs. The vocalization of «I province that he is sad» or «I province that such-and-such happened in the twelvemonth 1651» is infelicitous because you can non province something in absentia. so to talk ; in this instance. another person’s feelings or an event that took topographic point in 1651. hence a misdemeanor of the felicitousness status ( A. 2 ) .

I can non province something if I do non express the sentence right. Imagine that. alternatively of stating «I province I saw Sam and Ellie» . I. as a faux pas of the lingua. utter something which sounds more like «I province I saw salmonella» : I did non province «I saw Sam and Ellie» . as intended. therefore violating of the felicitousness status ( B. 1 ) . I can non province such-and-such if the listener is non listening to me. or thinks that I am jesting. hence a misdemeanor of the felicitousness status ( B. 2 ) .

Besides if I province such-and-such without believing it is the instance. the vocalization is infelicitous. hence a misdemeanor of the felicitousness status. Similarly. if I province such-and-such. and subsequently I refuse to do the same statement under the same fortunes. my earlier statement becomes instead questionable. hence in misdemeanor of the felicitousness status . These illustrations demonstrate that even an vocalization of the sentence of «I province …» . which would look to be more straight related to doing a statement instead than executing an act. is evaluated in footings of the elements of the address state of affairs. viz. . conventionality. actuality. and intentionality. and. consequently. is capable to infelicities related to them.

In the latter portion of the William James Lectures. Austin specifies performativity. once introduced as an intuitive thought of «performing an act» . He introduces the construct of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless. and carefully separate them from locutionary Acts of the Apostless and perlocutionary Acts of the Apostless. Locutionary Acts of the Apostless include phonic Acts of the Apostless. phatic Acts of the Apostless. and rhetic Acts of the Apostless. Phonetic Acts of the Apostless are Acts of the Apostless of articulating sounds. phatic Acts of the Apostless are Acts of the Apostless of uttering words or sentences in conformity with the phonological and syntactic regulations of the linguistic communication to which they belong. and rhetic Acts of the Apostless are Acts of the Apostless of expressing a sentence with sense and more or less definite mention. Perlocutionary Acts of the Apostless are. on the other manus. Acts of the Apostless attributed to the consequence of expressing a sentence.

Austin says that in expressing a sentence the talker performs an illocutionary act of holding a certain force. which is different from the locutionary act of expressing the sentence. which is to hold a significance. and besides from the perlocutionary act performed by expressing the sentence. which is to accomplish certain effects. By these differentiations. Capital of texas shows that. unlike locutionary Acts of the Apostless. illocutionary Acts of the Apostless have a force. and. unlike perlocutionary Acts of the Apostless. illocutionary Acts of the Apostless are valid and complete without being reduced to the consequence of it.

Austin classifies illocutionary Acts of the Apostless into five types. i. e. . verdictives. exercitives. commissives. behabitives. and expositives. Although it is frequently argued that Austin’s categorization is non complete and those coined classs are non reciprocally sole. Austin’s categorization is best seen as an effort to give a general image of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless: what types of illocutionary act one can by and large execute in expressing a sentence.

One can exert judgement ( Verdictive ) . exert influence or exercising power ( Exercitive ) . assume duty or declare purpose ( Commissive ) . adopt attitude. or express feeling ( Behabitive ) . and clarify grounds. statement. or communicating ( Expositive ) . The long list of illocutionary verbs in each category besides illustrates how many subtly differentiated illocutionary Acts of the Apostless exist in a linguistic communication like English. The fact that Austin includes the same word in two different categories and he does non see it as a job suggests that it is non an issue for Austin which category a peculiar illocutionary verb/act really belongs to.

The importance of presenting this categorization of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless is instead to explain. as we explained supra. what type of illocutionary act one can by and large execute by expressing a sentence ; and. with extra specifications. how much more diversified illocutionary Acts of the Apostless are than we are normally cognizant of.

The intent of the categorization of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless. if interpreted in this mode. is compatible with Austin’s beliefs as a major advocate of Ordinary Language Philosophy. which is typically expressed in comments such as the followers: our common stock of words embodies all the differentiations work forces have found worth pulling. and the connections they have found worth taging. in the life-times of many coevalss: these certainly are likely to be more legion. more sound. since they have stood up to the long trial of the endurance of the fittest. and more elusive. at least in all ordinary and moderately practical affairs. than any that you or I are likely to believe up in our arm-chairs of an afternoon — the most favoured alternate method. ( Austin 1961: 182 )

When we approach Austin’s address act theory from this angle. it highlights some of import issues addressed by Austin that still remain virtually untackled. By and large talking. the address act theoreticians after Austin focal point on explicating illocutionary Acts of the Apostless in a narrow sense. John Searle. a major advocate of the address act theory. inherits his thoughts from Austin and elaborates on some of them ( Searle 1969 ) . but develops the theory in his ain manner: the kernel of it being that to execute an illocutionary act is to show an illocutionary purpose ( Searle 1979 ) .

Searle’s impression of the address act theory is developed along this line. and Searle ( 1983 ) and Searle and Vanderveken ( 1985 ) effort to explicate illocutionary force in a formal theoretical account which is compatible with the formal analysis of propositional contents. Schiffer ( 1972 ) describes illocutionary Acts of the Apostless in footings of the speaker’s purpose to bring forth a certain response R in a certain audience. and the value ( s ) of «r» .

While each of these address act theories has some virtue. they are at odds with Austin’s original theory. In giving account of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless. the theoreticians have knowingly or inadvertently reduced them to something else. specifically. purposes. and they explain how one type of illocutionary act differs from another in footings of intentionality. This is. ironically. precisely what Austin criticised. With the construct of performatives. Austin demonstrated that significance of a sentence can non be to the full explained by one standard. i. e. . the propositional/descriptive content it expresses.

Austin besides emphasised the importance of depicting the entire address act in the entire address state of affairs in which the linguistic communication users employ the linguistic communication: the talker utters a sentence and performs a address act to the listener. While making so. Austin proposed ( I ) the felicitousness conditions. which define the elements in the public presentation of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless. ( II ) the differentiation between locutionary. illocutionary. and perlocutionary Acts of the Apostless. which specifies the sense of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless performed in footings of other Acts of the Apostless performed in communicating. and ( III ) the categorization of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless. which gives general thoughts of what Acts of the Apostless are performed and in footings of what they are specified.

In malice of the possibilities Austin suggested. these address act theorists persistently concentrate on explicating an illocutionary act in footings of an purpose. From Austin’s point of position. it is problematic whether cut downing significance. expressed by expressing a sentence. to the purpose is any better than cut downing it to a propositional/descriptive content which the sentence expresses. The intent of the present talk is to build a theoretical model in which to develop Austin’s original. unadulterated. address act theory. We begin with the hypothesis.

Speech act theoreticians after Austin failed to develop the address state of affairs construct. and they described illocutionary Acts of the Apostless in isolation. thereby asking an account of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless in footings of something else. or cut downing them to something else. such as purposes or attitudes. However. we propose that the most of import part by Austin was his development of the thought of the address state of affairs clarified by designation of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless. As the name suggests. the address state of affairs is a state of affairs which is. in one sense. a state of affairs merely like other state of affairss which are in a peculiar spatiotemporal location. but. in another sense. psychological infinite animated by lingual communicating and specified by lingual devices: it exists merely because I speak to you. and it doesn’t exist where there is no communicating.

This suggests that to express a sentence as a piece of communicating. i. e. . to execute a address act in a general sense. is to bespeak the address state of affairs where the sentence is expressed. every bit good as it expresses what the sentence is made to show. i. e. . a propositional/descriptive content. Austin’s construct of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless sheds visible radiation on the address state of affairs. and that it is indicated non merely as a general address state of affairs where the talker speaks to the listener. but besides as a more specified address state of affairs which varies in conventions activated. existent public presentations and reactions executed. and purposes expressed.

Austin’s initial construct of performatives in contrast to that of constatives accents this specification of the address state of affairs: to express a sentence such as «I name this ship the Queen Elizabeth» and «I bet six pence it will rain tomorrow» is to bespeak the address state of affairs. and it does non hold a separate descriptive content. To depict this facet of communicating. we have to first clear up the construct of the address state of affairs itself. and so explicate illocutionary Acts of the Apostless in relation to it. We explain executing an illocutionary act as follows: in expressing a sentence. the talker indicates a certain address state of affairs as the present address state of affairs. This. of class. needs account.

Merely like marks in general. lingual marks are to show something other than themselves. The word «apple» . as a lingual mark. does non intend the sound or a individual or a thing associated with expressing this sound: it merely means what it is made to intend. i. e. . a peculiar sort of fruit. Some words such as demonstratives are. on the other manus. self-reflexive: when an existent item of a word is expressed. it indicates a individual. thing. topographic point. or clip which is associated with expressing this item. For illustration. when the word «I» is expressed. it indicates the individual who utters this item. and when the word «now» is expressed. it indicates the clip of expressing this item.

If linguistic communication is equipped with this map. it is non hard to conceive of that this map is extended to the whole vocalization. Just like expressing the word «I» indicates the individual who utters this item. expressing a sentence such as «I name this ship the Queen Elizabeth» indicates the present address state of affairs where this vocalization is expressed. Furthermore. merely like the hearer/addressee is indicated by either a T-form or a V-form of the 2nd individual pronoun. in which the societal relation between the speaker/addresser and the hearer/addressee is implied. the vocalization of «I name this ship the Queen Elizabeth» indicates. as the present address state of affairs. a speech state of affairs of calling. which is linguistically differentiated from other state of affairss.

To explicate this we say: in expressing a sentence. the talker indicates a certain address state of affairs as the present address state of affairs. state of affairs. in footings of which a purported act succeeds/fails. We have suggested depicting these facets of the address state of affairs as the facet of conventionality. more explicitly. certain conventions activated ; the facet of actuality. more explicitly. certain public presentations and responses executed ; and the facet of intentionality. more explicitly. certain purposes expressed.

Conventionality. actuality. and intentionality of the address state of affairs Now we explain conventionality. actuality. and intentionality of the address state of affairs.Austin’s felicitousness conditions are as follows:( A. 1 ) There must be an recognized conventional process holding a certain conventional consequence. that process to include the uttering of certain words by certain individuals in certain fortunes. and further.

Where. as frequently. the process is designed for usage by individuals holding certain ideas or feelings. or for the startup of certain eventful behavior on the portion of any participant. so a individual take parting in and so raising the process must in fact have those ideas or feelings. and the participants must mean so to carry on themselves. and farther ( ? . 2 ) must really so conduct themselves later. ( Austin 1962: 1415 ) Misdemeanors of the conditions in ( A. 1 ) and ( A. 2 ) are described as «misinvocations» . in which the purported act is disallowed ( Austin 1962:18 ) . This. in bend. indicates the address state of affairs in which the purported act would be allowed.

The felicitousness status in ( A. 1 ) reveals an facet of the address state of affairs in which the talker and the listener portion lingual conventions harmonizing to which to express certain words in certain fortunes by certain individuals is counted as executing a certain address act. which has a certain conventional consequence. So the vocalization in illustration ( 1 ) indicates a address state of affairs in which the talker and the listener portion a Muslim convention of divorce: to express the sentence in ( 1 ) is counted as executing an act of divorce and. as a conventional consequence. divorce occurs.

Similarly the vocalization of the sentence in illustration ( 2 ) indicates a address state of affairs in which the talker and the listener portion the lingual convention of executing an act of rebuke: a certain action or the failure to take a certain action is capable to unfavorable judgment. and the responsible individual is to be blamed officially and publically for the disregard of her official responsibilities ( unlike the act of «telling person off» or chiding ) . by a individual in that official capacity. with conventional effects ( unlike the act of incrimination. unfavorable judgment. or reproach ) .

The felicitousness status in ( A. 2 ) reveals another facet of the address state of affairs. in which peculiar individuals and peculiar fortunes exist. So the vocalization in ( 3 ) indicates a address state of affairs in which the talker is a Christian priest and the listener is an baby. They are in spiritual fortunes. such as in a Christian church. and in the presence of the infant’s parents.

Similarly the vocalization in illustration ( 4 ) indicates a address state of affairs in which the talker and the listener have a formal. hierarchal relationship to one another. by which the talker can bear down the listener to put to death a certain action ( unlike the act of inquiring or imploring ) . and does so for his ain involvement instead than for the hearer’s ( unlike the act of leting or authorising ) . and noncompliance to the bid may hold terrible effects.

These scenarios set up that the address state of affairs can be specified linguistically. By stipulating the present act as divorce. rebuke. baptise. and order. the talker indicates. as the present address state of affairs. a address state of affairs where associated conventions are activated. and individuals and fortunes specified by those conventions are present. In other words. by stipulating what the talker is presently making in expressing what he utters. the talker specifies the address state of affairs which presently exists between him and the listener. Those specifications are dependent upon the linguistic communication. What is regarded as an act and how that act is specified in footings of related Acts of the Apostless are mostly determined by the linguistic communication that the talker uses. We describe this facet of the address state of affairs as conventionality of the address state of affairs.

A misdemeanor of the 2nd type of status in ( B. 1 ) and ( B. 2 ) is described as «misexecutions» . in which a purported act is vitiated ( Austin 1962:18 ) . This. in bend. depicts a address state of affairs in which a purported act would be executed in a really specific mode.

The felicitousness status in ( B. 1 ) describes an facet of the present address state of affairs in which the present talker really utters words in a specific mode to the present listener. That is. in expressing a sentence. the talker presents himself as the performing artist of a certain act to the present listener: in expressing a sentence. the talker conveys that I perform this act to you. In stipulating the act as. say. an act of rebuke. the talker indicates the present address state of affairs in which the talker ( I ) performs this act of rebuke to the listener ( you ) . The felicitousness status in ( B. 2 ) exposes another facet of the present address state of affairs which is acknowledged and revitalised by the listener.

The present address state of affairs indicated by the talker as a certain state of affairs can either be acknowledged and revitalized by the listener who behaves/responds in a given mode. or be dismissed by the listener who does non make so. For illustration. when the talker indicates the present address state of affairs as a state of affairs of an order in expressing the sentence in ( 4 ) . i. e. the talker indicates that I perform to you this act of an order. the listener may admit and revitalize it by bespeaking that he is following the order.

Alternatively. the listener may merely let go of the captives. We explain this facet of the address state of affairs as actuality. in which existent public presentation and response are executed. Austin’s felicitousness conditions in ( A ) and ( B ) allude to two different ways in which address acts fail. They fail because the conventional processs for executing Acts of the Apostless do non be or those processs are such that they can non be applied to peculiar instances. They besides fail because existent public presentations do non match to conventional processs: the talker merely makes a error and produces a incorrect sound. produces an unhearable sound. misunderstands conventional processs for the public presentation of a specific act. or the listener does non admit the purported act.

These infelicitous instances. in bend. expose felicitous instances where existent public presentations correspond to conventional processs. i. e. . a purported act is the act really performed by the present talker: an indicated address state of affairs is the present address state of affairs. This is the point at which abstract convention coincides with physical public presentation. In one sense. this is the point at which a convention is actualized as a portion of the world with its substance. i. e. . an existent illocutionary act ; and. in another sense. it is the point at which an action. which is in itself inadvertent and pointless. is specified by the linguistic communication as a system of value.

Austin says: The first large differentiation is between all the four regulations A and B taken together. as opposed to the two regulations ? ( hence the usage of Roman as opposed to Greek letters ) . If we offend against any of the former regulations ( A’s or B’s ) —that is if we. state. express the expression falsely. or if. say. we are non in a place to make the act because we are. state. married already. or it is the purser and non the captain who is carry oning the ceremonial. so the act in inquiry. e. g. marrying. is non successfully performed at all. does non come off. is non achieved. Whereas in the two  instances the act is achieved. although to accomplish it in such fortunes. as when we are. state. insincere. is an maltreatment of process. Therefore. when I say ‘I promise’ and have no purpose of maintaining it.

The instances of maltreatment which are clarified by felicitousness conditions in and  hence. uncover a address state of affairs where the professed act is sincere and significant: the talker means what she says and intends to carry through her future duty. For illustration. in expressing the sentence: I welcome you. the talker demonstrates herself as a sincere performing artist of this act of welcome: the talker is truly delighted to hold the listener in her company. such as a topographic point or an organisation.

In other words. the talker indicates the present address state of affairs as a state of affairs where the act of welcome is sincere and significant. Specifically. the talker means what she says. and she approves of and is delighted by the hearer’s presence. This is the facet of intentionality of the present address state of affairs. which the felicitousness status in ( ? . 1 ) clarifies. Another facet of intentionality. which the felicitousness status clarifies. concerns a future duty. That is. the present address state of affairs is indicated non merely as a state of affairs where a purported act is sincere and significant. but besides as a state of affairs where associated future committedness is expressed. For illustration. in expressing the sentence:

I promise to back up you. the talker indicates the present address state of affairs as a state of affairs which does non be merely at the clip of vocalization but which will last for a longer period of clip. wherein the speaker’s support for the listener is promised. That is. the felicitousness conditions in and  clear up how the present address state of affairs is substantiated by the speaker’s associated purpose and future duty expressed. The construction of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless which we have described would look to be a beginning of force. Conventions do non do a move in communicating. Accidental/pointless actions do non hold value in themselves. And purposes are obscure in nature. However. an existent act which is performed on the footing of lingual conventions. and strengthened by associated purposes expressed by the talker has a force in communicating.

Such an act has ( I ) a lingual value. e. g. an act of divorce or welcome ; ( II ) a concrete artifact with substance ; and ( III ) it is an look of the speaker’s purpose. In other words. the public presentation of an illocutionary act makes the present address state of affairs a certain address state of affairs specified by the convention. and strengthened by the present speaker’s expressed purpose. As we suggested earlier. Austin proposes an alternate theoretical account of significance. It is non simply to explicate conventional dealingss between sentences and provinces of personal businesss. or between sentences and purposes.

Rather. to explicate significance. Austin implicates lingual artifacts. i. e. . illocutionary Acts of the Apostless. which are created by lingual conventions. existent public presentation. and the speaker’s expressed purposes. We reanalyse this account. and suggest to handle the artifacts as Acts of the Apostless that indicate the address state of affairs: to execute illocutionary Acts of the Apostless is to bespeak. as the present address state of affairs. a certain state of affairs. which is substantiated by an associated purpose expressed. The aforesaid constructs of conventionality. actuality. and intentionality describe these facets of the address state of affairs.

This represents a unitary position of significance. Meaning is explained by an scrutiny of lingual conventions ( contained in a linguistic communication ) . existent public presentation ( linguistic communication usage ) . and associated purposes. In linguistics the general inclination is to depict one facet of significance as if it were the kernel of significance. In semantics. lingual conventions are by and large explained by correlating sentences with provinces of personal businesss. In pragmatics. existent public presentations are studied to depict a certain type or facet of communicating. Intentionality is described. semantically. in footings of the relation between sentences and associated purposes.

Or it is described. pragmatically. as existent public presentations in which the talker expresses his purposes. As a consequence. semantics theories tend to offer the lingual agencies that are available to the users without explicating how those agencies are used to do communicating possible. Whereas matter-of-fact theories tend to explicate what is go oning in communicating without explicating the available lingual agencies. Austin’s theory is assuring because it unites all three facets of significance. viz. lingual conventions. linguistic communication usage. and intentionality.

In this sense. it is a believable general theory of communicating. Another singularity of Austin’s theory lies in the fact that significance is explained in a non-tautological manner. In correspondence theories of significance. a sentence is correlated. as its significance. with a province of personal businesss. However. the province of personal businesss correlated with the sentence is non an existent province of personal businesss in the universe. but instead a province of personal businesss which is segmented by the sentence in inquiry. That is. to explicate what a sentence expresses is to explicate how the sentence is different in intending from other sentences.

And. since the sentence expresses what it expresses because of sentence structure and semantics of the linguistic communication. to explicate significance of the sentence is to explicate sentence structure and semantics of the linguistic communication. Therefore. to explicate significance is non to explicate what a sentence means in communicating nor what the talker means in expressing a sentence. It explains the linguistic communication by situating another abstract degree of the linguistic communication. This is what Tarski does by his theory of truth in his celebrated illustration:  «Snow is white» is true if and merely if snow is white. where the phrase «Snow is white» on the left side of this equality in inquiry Markss belongs to an object linguistic communication and the 1 on the right without citation Markss belongs to meta-language.

The sentence of an object linguistic communication «Snow is white» is true if and merely if «snow» designates snow and snow satisfies the sentential map. «x is white» . ( Tarski 1944: 585 ) Furthermore. Tarski allows more than one abstract degree of the linguistic communication. He says: It should be noticed that these footings «object-language» and «metalanguage» have merely a comparative sense. If. for case. we become interested in the impression of truth using to sentences. non of our original objectlanguage. but of its meta-language. the latter becomes automatically the object-language of our treatment: and in order to specify truth for this linguistic communication. we have to travel to a new meta-language — so to talk. to a metalanguage of a higher degree. In this manner. we arrive at a whole hierarchy of linguistic communications. ( Tarski 1944: 597-598 )

Then to explicate significance is to explicate the semantic system of the linguistic communication in inquiry by situating one or more abstract degrees of the linguistic communication. non to explicate what the talker means in utilizing the linguistic communication. Austin’s address act theory. nevertheless. theoretically distinguishes the linguistic communication. the present address state of affairs. and the purposes of the present talker.

As Austin’s felicitousness conditions in ( A ) show. a purported address act can be infelicitous because of the linguistic communication. i. e. lingual conventions. irrespective of existent public presentations in the address state of affairs and the purpose of the present talker. As the felicitousness conditions in ( B ) show. an existent public presentation can be infelicitous in its ain manner irrespective of the lingual conventions and the present speaker’s purpose. And. eventually. as the felicitousness conditions in show. a address act can be abused irrespective of the lingual conventions and the public presentation of the present talker. So to depict lingual conventions. to depict an existent public presentation in the address state of affairs. and to depict the speaker’s purpose expressed are theoretically independent ofone another.

For this ground. the success of the address act is explained as the happenstance of these three typical elements: a purported act becomes the act performed. which is substantiated by an associated purpose expressed. We have proposed to explicate executing an illocutionary act as follows: in expressing a sentence. the talker indicates. as the present address state of affairs. a certain address state of affairs ( specified by lingual conventions ) . which is substantiated by an associated purpose of the present talker. When there is no spread among these. i. e. the present address state of affairs. a address state of affairs indicated. and the purposes of the talker expressed. the purported act is successful: the present address state of affairs becomes an indicated address state of affairs. with the purpose expressed. Harmonizing to this theory. the linguistic communication. that is lingual conventions. expresses things outside of the system of the linguistic communication.

Decision

We have expanded on Austin’s address act theory so that «the entire address state of affairs in the entire address situation» can be better understood. Unlike other address act theoreticians who basically depict how illocutionary Acts of the Apostless differ from one another in footings of intentionality. we have proposed an alternate strategy: to depict illocutionary Acts of the Apostless in footings of different facets of the address state of affairs.

After ab initio discoursing the address state of affairs and its theoretical import. and later utilizing Austin’s felicitousness conditions as a starting point. we illustrated three facets of the address state of affairs. conventionality. actuality. and intentionality. harmonizing to which a purported act succeeds or fails. And following we explained the public presentation of an illocutionary act as follows: by expressing a sentence. the talker indicates. as the present address state of affairs. a certain address state of affairs. which is substantiated by an associated purpose.

The intent of the present paper is simply to supply a theoretical model. through an analysis of illocutionary Acts of the Apostless. which gives a clearer and more concise description of the address state of affairs on which communicating is based. To really «enflesh» this model. more thorough analyses of the address state of affairs and both types of address act are needed.

Mentions

  1. Austin. John L. . A supplication for alibis. «Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society» ; reprinted in J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock ( explosive detection systems. ) . Philosophic Papers. Oxford University Press. Oxford 1956. pp. 175-204.
  2. Austin. John L. . How to Make Thingss with Words. Clarendon. Oxford 1962. Brown. Penelope. Levinson. Stephen C. . Politeness: Some universals in linguistic communication use. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge 1987.
  3. Esercizi Filosofici 1. 2006 / TestiDowty. David R. . Wall. Robert E. . Stanley. Peters. Introduction to Montague Semantics. Reidel. Dordrecht 1981.Oishi. Etsuko. «Semantic significance and four types of address act» . in P. Kuhnlein. H. Riser and H. Zeevat ( explosive detection systems. ) . Positions on Dialogue in the New Millennium. John Benjamins. Amsterdam 2003. pp. 135-147.
  4. Russell. Bertrand. On denoting. «Mind» . 14. 1905 ; reprinted in T. M. Olshewsky ( ed. ) . Problems in the Philosophy of Language. Holt. Rinehart and Winston. New York 1969. pp. 300-311. Schiffer. Stephen R. . Meaning. Oxford University Press. Oxford 1972. Searle. John R. . Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge 1969.
  5. Searle. John R. . «Indirect speech acts» . in P. Cole. J. L. Morgan ( explosive detection systems. ) . Syntax and Semantics 3: Address Acts. Academic Press. New York 1975.Searle. John R. . Expression and Meaning: Surveies in the Theory of Speech Act. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge 1979. Searle. John R. . Intentionality: An essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge 1983.
  6. Searle. John R. . «How performatives work» . in D. Vanderveken. S. Kubo ( explosive detection systems. ) . Essaies in Speech Act Theory. John Benjamins. Amsterdam 2001. pp. 85-117.Searle. John R. . Vanderveken. Daniel. Foundations of Illocutionary Logic. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge. 1985.Tarski. Alfred. The semantic construct of truth. «Philosophy and Phenomenological Research» . V. 1944 ; reprinted in T. M. Olshewsky ( ed. ) . Problems in the Philosophy of Language. Holt. Rinehart and Winston. New York 1944. pp. 578-610.
  7. Vanderveken. Daniel. Kubo. Susumu. Essaies in Speech Act Theory. John Benjamins. Amsterdam 2001.Warnock. G. J. . English Philosophy since 1900. Oxford University Press. Oxford 1969.

Cite this page

Austin’s Speech Act Theory and the Speech Situation Sample. (2017, Aug 13). Retrieved from

https://graduateway.com/austins-speech-act-theory-and-the-speech-situation-essay-sample-essay/

Remember! This essay was written by a student

You can get a custom paper by one of our expert writers

Order custom paper Without paying upfront